Access the full text.
Sign up today, get DeepDyve free for 14 days.
H. Butterfield (1950)
The Origins of Modern Science: 1300-1800
H. Cohen (2013)
Two New Conceptions of the Scientific Revolution ComparedHistorically Speaking, 14
R. Westfall, M. Klein (1971)
The Construction of Modern Science: Mechanisms and Mechanics
J. Smith, E. Burtt (1967)
In Search of Philosophic Understanding.The Philosophical Review, 78
H. Cook (2007)
Matters of Exchange: Commerce, Medicine, and Science in the Dutch Golden Age
Pamela Long, H. Cohen (1994)
The Scientific Revolution: A Historiographical Inquiry
T. Kuhn (1976)
Mathematical vs. Experimental Traditions in the Development of Physical ScienceJournal of Interdisciplinary History, 7
D. Villemaire (2002)
E.A. Burtt, Historian and Philosopher
E. Dijksterhuis (1935)
Val en worp : een bijdrage tot de geschiedenis der mechanica van Aristoteles tot Newton
J. Burckhardt (2009)
Die Kultur der Renaissance in Italien: ein Versuch
H. Cohen (2012)
How Modern Science Came into the World: Four Civilizations, One 17th-Century Breakthrough
E. Burtt
The Metaphysical Foundations of Modern Physical Science : A Historical and Critical Essay
Pieter Kollewijn, E. Dijksterhuis (1951)
De mechanisering van het wereldbeeld
[The concept of ‘the mathematization of nature’ arose in close connection with the equally novel concept of ‘The Scientific Revolution of the seventeenth century’. The pioneers were DijksterhuisDijksterhuis, Eduard Jan (1892-1965) (Val en worp. Een bijdrage tot de geschiedenis der mechanica van Aristoteles tot Newton. Noordhoff, Groningen, 1924), BurttBurtt, Edwin Arthur (1892-1989) (The Metaphysical Foundations of Modern Physical Science. A Historical and Critical Essay, Routledge & Kegan Paul, London, 1924), and KoyréKoyré, Alexandre (1892-1964) (Etudes Galiléennes. Hermann, Paris, 1939/1940). Thanks in good part to KoyréKoyré, Alexandre (1892-1964)’s agenda-driven perseverance, these became highly productive concepts. Nonetheless their analytically sharp delineation quickly gave way to an unceasing process of meaning dilution. In the 1970s KuhnKuhn, Thomas Samuel (1922-1996) and WestfallWestfall, Richard S. (1924-1996) sought (but to little avail) to halt the process by suggesting two ingenious ‘two-current’ accounts of the Scientific Revolution, with the mathematization of nature figuring prominently in each. The idea of the mathematization of nature being key to the Scientific Revolution has kept informing a ‘master narrative’ that professionals have ever since the 1980s tended to regard as hopelessly obsolete. It is certainly true that, in their original guise, these concepts are incapable of capturing fundamental aspects of the pursuit of knowledge of nature in seventeenth century Europe. But is that good enough a reason to give them up altogether? Two efforts at fresh reconceptualization have recently been undertaken, one by GaukrogerGaukroger, Stephen (*1950), one by the author of the present chapter. Having compared the two elsewhere, he outlines here in what ways he has partly reinstated, partly revised, partly expanded, but in all cases built forth upon, the still vital notion of the mathematization of nature. In this partly altered guise, it marks three of the six revolutionary transformations that in his view comprise the Scientific Revolution of the seventeenth century.]
Published: Dec 9, 2016
Keywords: Scientific Revolution; Mathematization of nature
Read and print from thousands of top scholarly journals.
Already have an account? Log in
Bookmark this article. You can see your Bookmarks on your DeepDyve Library.
To save an article, log in first, or sign up for a DeepDyve account if you don’t already have one.
Copy and paste the desired citation format or use the link below to download a file formatted for EndNote
Access the full text.
Sign up today, get DeepDyve free for 14 days.
All DeepDyve websites use cookies to improve your online experience. They were placed on your computer when you launched this website. You can change your cookie settings through your browser.