Access the full text.
Sign up today, get DeepDyve free for 14 days.
G. Hegel, Sir Knox (1975)
Aesthetics: Lectures on Fine Art, Vol. 2: Lectures on Fine Art
胤久 小田部 (1990)
マンフレッド・フランク, 『初期ロマン派の美学への入門・講義』, Manfred Frank, Einfuhrung in die fruhromantische Asthetik, Vorlesungen, Suhrkamp, Frankfurt am Main 1989, 462S., 41
Andrew Bowie (2018)
Aesthetics and subjectivity from Kant to Nietzsche
Frederick Beiser (2003)
The Romantic Imperative: The Concept of Early German Romanticism
Detlev Schottker (1997)
Fragment und Traktat. Walter Benjamin und die aphoristische tradition, 43
Martin Weatherston (1996)
KANT'S ASSESSMENT OF MUSIC IN THE CRITIQUE OF JUDGMENTBritish Journal of Aesthetics, 36
P. Krause (2001)
Unbestimmte Rhetorik : Friedrich Schlegel und die Redekunst um 1800Modern Language Review, 98
G. Hegel, T. Knox (1975)
Aesthetics : lectures on fine art
Ian Balfour, Phillipe Lacoue-Labarthe, J. Nancy, P. Barnard, Cheryl Lester (1988)
The Literary Absolute: The Theory of Literature in German Romanticism.Mln, 104
Azade Seyhan (1992)
Representation and Its Discontents: The Critical Legacy of German Romanticism
Charles Rosen (1996)
The Romantic Generation
John Daverio (1987)
Symmetry and chaos: Friedrich Schlegel's views on musicNineteenth-century Contexts, 11
[As the symphonies of Joseph Haydn and Wolfgang Amadeus Mozart were resounding throughout the late eighteenth-century concert halls of Berlin, Dresden, and Jena, a 25-year-old Friedrich Schlegel was scribbling fragments in his literary notebooks about music with “sublime audacity” (KA, 24: 31).1 Although he never developed these fragments into a comprehensive theory of musical aesthetics, numerous remarks on music can be found scattered throughout his many aesthetic, literary, and philosophical writings. Unlike for the early German Romantic writers Friedrich von Hardenburg (Novalis), Ludwig Tieck, and Heinrich Wilhelm Wackenroder, music did not serve as a key theoretical axis of his philosophical project. However, contrary to the contentions of earlier scholarship, Schlegel was neither insensitive nor oblivious to music’s inherent aesthetic potentiality.2 Even though he was never, strictly speaking, a music aficionado, Schlegel was very familiar with contemporary debates on music. While studying classical Greek culture, for example, he carefully read the first volume of Johann Nicolaus Forkel’s A General History of Music (1788), which is widely considered to be the first modern work of musicology. In two letters to his older brother, August Wilhelm, in 1795, Schlegel caustically dismisses Forkel’s ahistorical reduction of music into a system of rhetorical strategies as inherently flawed (KA, 23: 226, 251).3 This negative evaluation of rhetorically deducible effects would soon resonate throughout his entire cultural critique.]
Published: Nov 2, 2015
Keywords: Rhetorical Strategy; Musical Work; Musical Signifier; German Culture; Transcendental Philosophy
Read and print from thousands of top scholarly journals.
Already have an account? Log in
Bookmark this article. You can see your Bookmarks on your DeepDyve Library.
To save an article, log in first, or sign up for a DeepDyve account if you don’t already have one.
Copy and paste the desired citation format or use the link below to download a file formatted for EndNote
Access the full text.
Sign up today, get DeepDyve free for 14 days.
All DeepDyve websites use cookies to improve your online experience. They were placed on your computer when you launched this website. You can change your cookie settings through your browser.