Get 20M+ Full-Text Papers For Less Than $1.50/day. Start a 14-Day Trial for You or Your Team.

Learn More →

Understanding ImaginationAristotle’s phantasia: From Animal Sensation to Understanding Forms of Fields

Understanding Imagination: Aristotle’s phantasia: From Animal Sensation to Understanding Forms of... [What imagination is cannot be answered apart from understanding its conceptual topology, the articulated framework of basic phenomena and concepts that govern our thinking about it. The second step toward this goal is to grasp how Aristotle (384–322 B.C.E.) exploited and revolutionized the basic “topography” or “matrix” of being–and–soul that his master Plato had laid down. Aristotle made a claim that became the “default position” about imagination for two millennia: that there is no thinking (thus also no knowing) without images. He shifted the center of gravity for imagination studies from the ontology of images that Plato had emphasized to a physiologically based psychology of imagining, which he first embedded in the psychology of animal being and then modified in the human animal by the presence of reason. Although parts of Aristotle’s philosophy of imagination are elusive—in particular the radical distance between animal and human imagination—and were distorted by later traditions, it makes a great deal more sense when it is seen against the background of his physical theories. An exploration of these connections not only explains his theory’s influence and durability but also why it still provides a unifying basis for understanding contemporary cognitive and biological approaches. Moreover, his theory offers hitherto unexploited resources for more accurately conceiving images as emergent, as variable phenomena that are indispensable for acquiring knowledge and guiding human action.] http://www.deepdyve.com/assets/images/DeepDyve-Logo-lg.png

Understanding ImaginationAristotle’s phantasia: From Animal Sensation to Understanding Forms of Fields

Loading next page...
 
/lp/springer-journals/understanding-imagination-aristotle-s-phantasia-from-animal-sensation-YNAi3KM1zP

References (22)

Publisher
Springer Netherlands
Copyright
© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2013
ISBN
978-94-007-6506-1
Pages
185 –265
DOI
10.1007/978-94-007-6507-8_5
Publisher site
See Chapter on Publisher Site

Abstract

[What imagination is cannot be answered apart from understanding its conceptual topology, the articulated framework of basic phenomena and concepts that govern our thinking about it. The second step toward this goal is to grasp how Aristotle (384–322 B.C.E.) exploited and revolutionized the basic “topography” or “matrix” of being–and–soul that his master Plato had laid down. Aristotle made a claim that became the “default position” about imagination for two millennia: that there is no thinking (thus also no knowing) without images. He shifted the center of gravity for imagination studies from the ontology of images that Plato had emphasized to a physiologically based psychology of imagining, which he first embedded in the psychology of animal being and then modified in the human animal by the presence of reason. Although parts of Aristotle’s philosophy of imagination are elusive—in particular the radical distance between animal and human imagination—and were distorted by later traditions, it makes a great deal more sense when it is seen against the background of his physical theories. An exploration of these connections not only explains his theory’s influence and durability but also why it still provides a unifying basis for understanding contemporary cognitive and biological approaches. Moreover, his theory offers hitherto unexploited resources for more accurately conceiving images as emergent, as variable phenomena that are indispensable for acquiring knowledge and guiding human action.]

Published: Apr 1, 2013

Keywords: Common Sensation; Sense Organ; Local Motion; Physical Thing; External Sense

There are no references for this article.